“If the law
supposes that,” said Mr. Bumble, squeezing his hat emphatically in both hands, “the
law is an ass―an idiot. If that’s the eye of the law, the law is a bachelor;
and the worst I wish the law is, that his eye may be opened by experience—by
experience.”
―Charles
Dickens, “Oliver Twist”, Chapter 51
First allow
me these three preliminary fictitious examples before bringing it all back home:
EXAMPLE 1
Suppose a
seasoned pilot, given his expertise, can execute highly complex and
life-threatening mid-air manoeuvres in any which way possible. He would often, and
against regulations, take passengers aboard on some of his aforementioned exploits;
each and every time succeeding in executing these escapades with textbook
aplomb. One day the plane crashed. Ten of his fourteen passengers died and the
other four were injured seriously. Our pilot himself had also been seriously
injured and spent five days in hospital, escaping death by a narrow margin. He is charged with ten counts of murder in
respect of the deceased and four of the attempt thereof in respect of the
injured. The prosecution knew that proving murder with direct intent would be out
of the question (perhaps understandably so). Instead they relied on murder with
legal intent (dolus eventuaslis). What
had to be proved therefore was that the accused: (i) subjectively foresaw the
possibility of the deaths ensuing from his conduct; and (ii) reconciled himself
with that possibility.
The Judge found
that requirement (i) had been proved―so far, so good. However, the court found
in favour of the accused regarding requirement (ii). Thus spoke the Judge: “The
accused is not guilty of the ten murders in that he had not, for the following
reasons, reconciled himself with the possibility of these deaths ensuing:
·
the accused is a qualified and
seasoned pilot;
·
he had each and every time
before successfully indulged similar quixotic
exploits with or without passengers on board;
·
therefore, this time around he also subjectively
entertained the possibility that he would succeed;
·
this subjective believe having thus
been established, entailed that he had not reconciled himself with the
possibility of these deaths ensuing;
·
furthermore, this accused himself
suffered serious injuries;
·
if it were held that he had reconciled
himself with the possibility of these deaths, it would mean that he must also have
reconciled himself with the consequence of his own;
·
and such possibility could hardly be
imputed to him.
[The Judge thereupon, for reasons I need not entertain here, convicted on
ten counts of culpable homicide and acquitted on all four attempts thereof]
EXAMPLE 2
1.
A gunman inserts one round in a revolver, spins the cylinder, and
puts the barrel against the head of a willing participant. However, he also
places the back of his own hand flat against the participant’s head. This is ostensibly
his guarantee to the participant whom he thereby purports to assure that he is absolutely
subjectively convinced that the gun will not discharge.; in the unlikely event
of this, the bullet would then have to hit his own hand also; this the
participant could rest assured the gunman would not risk. Then he would pull
the trigger and the gun does not fire. This
happens umpteenth times. However, one day he pulled a trigger too many, blowing
away his participant‘s head. He himself is admitted to hospital, stays there
for five days, almost having died of loss of blood.
He is acquitted of murder for the
very reason that he had been dabbling in his version of Russian roulette on
many a successful occasion, that every time when he had pulled the trigger, no bullet
had ever been discharged. He could therefore not now suddenly be adjudged to have
subjectively reconciled himself with the possibility that his game of chance would
literally back fire
Furthermore, had not he himself almost
died in his own adventure? This being the case, how could it possibly be held that
the accused could ever have reconciled himself with the deceased’s dying without
absurdly first contemplating that he had reconciled himself with his own
demise?
EXAMPLE 3
Counsel
for a serial rapist, now charged with murder upon the death of one of his
victims, argues as follows:
“M’Lord,
my client is used to sexually violating his victims. He’d done it many, a many
time. His trademark, over and above the sexual assaults had been to scar each
victim by methodically slashing their faces with a sharp knife. M’Lord as the
forensic psychologist testified, it’s in the very nature of his sadistic endeavours
that he must abide by this procedure, he relishes in this, he prides himself on
this, these knife wounds are obsessive condiciones
sine quibus non (conditions to his violent sexual assaults without which
his crimes could not be). He had been doing this with surgical precision. Deviation
from this ritual would not match his psychological make-up. In fact M’Lord this
was what the forensic psychologist (the State’s own witness) testified. In casu he had once more taken utmost
care to stick to his obsessive behaviour: a sexual assault, followed by the
slashing of the deceased face several times. M’Lord, how could this
professional mutilator of his victims’ bodies have reconciled himself thereof that
suddenly this time around there would (and this is my respectful submission) be
an unfortunate accident resulting in his also slitting the deceased throat? He
had never been a murderer simply because he prides himself on his meticulous
textbook mutilation of his victim’s faces only. Subjective reconciliation of the
possibility of death ensuing, given the forensic psychologist’s expert evidence,
would be anathema to my client’s way of doing things.”
“And besides,
when the knife slipped, my client accidently also cut his own wrist and
sustained such severe injuries that he spent five full days in hospital and he himself
escaped death narrowly. If it were argued that my client had reconciled himself
with the possibility of the deceased dying, then it would absurdly have to be
conceded that my client had subjectively reconciled himself with his own death
ensuing. And this M’Lord, I respectfully submit would defy logic!’
Lest you might
regard all these examples as farfetched, let now consider the judgment of Brand
JA in S v Humphreys 2013 (2) SACR 1
(SCA). I quote:
[1] The appellant, then in his late
fifties, was charged in the Western Cape High Court, Cape Town before Henney J
with ten counts of murder and four counts of attempted murder. All these
charges arose from a single incident which occurred on 25 August 2010 when a
minibus, driven by the appellant, was hit by a train on a railway crossing near
Blackheath on the outskirts of Cape Town. There were fourteen children in the
minibus, ranging in ages between seven and sixteen years. Ten of the children
were fatally injured in the collision, which gave rise to the ten charges of
murder. Four of them fortunately survived, but were seriously injured. They
were cited as the complainants in the four charges of attempted murder. At the
end of the trial the appellant was convicted as charged on all fourteen counts
and sentenced to an effective period of 20 years’ imprisonment.
[4] What then happened, according to
the eyewitnesses was that the appellant overtook the line of vehicles on their
right-hand side and approached the crossing in the lane destined for oncoming
traffic. The crossing is controlled by two booms in Buttskop Road, one for
traffic from the east – as the appellant was approaching – and the other for
traffic from the west. Because the booms are positioned on different sides of
the railway line, they can be avoided, even when they are down, by going onto the
lane intended for oncoming traffic and by then returning to the correct lane to
pass the boom on the other side. On both sides of the railway line there are
also large stop signs as well as other traffic signs indicating a railway
crossing. In addition there are large red warning lights directed at traffic in
Buttskop Road that start flashing when a train approaches the crossing and just
before the booms come down.
On appeal this accused’s four murder convictions
(as with our fictitious accused above) were reduced to culpable homicide. [He
was furthermore completely acquitted of all four attempted murder charges, but
this note does not deal with this aspect]
Here is another
excerpt from the SCA judgment, in justification for reducing Judge Hennery’s
convictions of murder to that of culpable homicide.
18] . . . . Put differently, the appellant must have been
indifferent as to whether he would live or die. But there is no indication on
the evidence that the appellant valued his own life any less than the average
person or that it was immaterial to him whether or not he would lose his life.
In consequence I do not think it can be said that the appellant had reconciled
himself with the possibility of his own death.
[19] My
second reason for concluding that the appellant did not reconcile himself with
the consequences rests on the evidence that the appellant had successfully
performed the same manoeuvre in virtually the same circumstances previously.
Let me summarise Brand JA as follows:
1.
the
accused himself had been seriously injured when the trail hit his taxi, therefore he could hardly be said to
have reconciled himself subjectively with the ten deceased dying; such
conclusion would mean that he had subjectively reconciled himself with his own
death;
2.
the
accused’s previous adventurous exploits, having courted disaster and getting away
with it, made assured him subjectively that he could in this matter survive again;
3.
a
seasoned risk-taker, he could therefore not have reconciled himself
subjectively with the possibility that he would fail this time around, with
death as a consequence.
It would be presumptuous of me to criticise
Brand JA on his exposition of the law relating to dolus eventualis. It would even be presumptuous to agree with the
learned Judge of Appeal (which by the way, I do). But this having been conceded,
suffice it to say that, If the law supposes this (which I am
afraid it does), then the law is an ass―an idiot. And so am I.
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteA CRIMINAL LAW CASE STUDY
ReplyDeleteInjuries inflicted Intentionally (wilfully) vs. Injuries inflicted negligently (carelessly)
The accused INTENTIONALLY (willfully) attacks another person. He can be convicted of assault or (if it is proved that he intended to kill the victim but the victim survives) he can be convinced of attempted murder. Where an accused injures (but not kills) another person non-intentionally / non-wilfully but only NEGLIGENTLY (carelessly), the Criminal Law does not provide for a conviction. This accused will be acquired (set free). In the discussion below the accused drove his vehicle negligently. In the case of the occupants that were only INJURED he was acquired of Attempted Murder, because he “assaulted” them negligently (carelessly) only and NOT intentionally /wilfully.
from the Appeal Court Judgement:
ReplyDelete“[1] The appellant, then in his late fifties, was charged in the Western Cape High Court, Cape Town before Henney J ( the Blogger's former colleague Bellville Magistratrs’ Court, now High Court Judge) with ten counts of murder and four counts of attempted murder. All these charges arose from a single incident which occurred on 25 August 2010 when a minibus, driven by the appellant, was hit by a train on a railway crossing near Blackheath on the outskirts of Cape Town. There were fourteen children in the minibus, ranging in ages between seven and sixteen years. Ten of the children were fatally injured in the collision, which gave rise to the ten charges of murder. Four of them fortunately survived, but were seriously injured. They were cited as the complainants in the four charges of attempted murder. At the end of the trial the appellant was convicted as charged on all fourteen counts and sentenced to an effective period of 20 years’ imprisonment.