Wednesday, 9 October 2013

LITERARY LEGAL QUOTATIONS — PART 3

MILAN KUNDERA


Murder simply hastens a bit what God will eventually see to on His own. God, it may be assumed, took murder into account; . . .

The Unbearable Lightness of Being


    But, he said to himself, whether they knew or didn’t know is not the main issue; the main issue is whether a man is innocent because he didn’t know. Is a fool on the throne relieved of all responsibility merely because he is a fool?
    Let us concede that a Czech public prosecutor in the early fifties who called for the death of an innocent man was deceived by the Russian secret police and the government of his own country. But now that we all know the accusations to have been absurd and the execution to have been innocent, how can that selfsame public prosecutor defend his purity of heart by beating himself on the chest and proclaiming, My conscience is clear! I didn’t know! I was a believer! Isn’t his “I didn’t know! I was a believer!” at the very root of his irreparable guilt?
    It was in this connection that Tomas recalled the tale of Oedipus: Oedipus did not know he was sleeping with his own mother, yet when he realized what had happened, he did not feel innocent. Unable to stand the sight of the misfortunes he had wrought by “not knowing,” he put out his eyes and wandered blind away from Thebes.

The Unbearable Lightness of Being


     His act of murder was a strange one: murder without a motive. Nothing was to be gained by it. Then what sense did it make? Clearly, its only sense was to make him see that he was a murderer.
     Murder as experiment, as an act of self-revelation, this was a familiar story: the story of Raskolnikov. He murdered in order to answer for himself the question: Does man have the right to kill an inferior human being, and would he be strong enough to bear the consequences? The murder was a question posed to his own self.

The Farewell Party


. . . There was one thing I had learned after a year in prison: A prisoner needs at least his one certainty ─ that he is master of his own death, capable of choosing its time and manner. When you have that certainty, you can stand almost anything. You always know it is in your power to escape life anytime you choose.

The Farewell Party


. . . I’ll tell you the saddest discovery of my life: The victims are no better than their oppressors. I can easily imagine the roles reversed. You can call it a kind of alibi-ism, an attempt to evade responsibility and to blame everything on the Creator Who made man the way he is. And maybe it’s good that you see things that way. Because to come to the conclusion that there is no difference between the guilty and their victims is to reach a state where you abandon all hope. And that, my dear, is a definition of hell.”

The Farewell Party


. . . “Are you one of those people who call abortion ‘murder’?”
     Bartleff kept a lengthy silence. At last he emerged from the bathroom, fully dressed and neatly combed.
     “’Murder’ is a word that smells too much of the hangman’s noose”, he said. I am concerned about something else. You know, I believe that life is to be accepted totally and completely. That’s the very first commandment which has precedence over the other ten. Everything that is about to happen today is in the hands of God, and we know nothing of tomorrow. What I am trying to say is that total acceptance of life means acceptance of the unforeseen. And a child is the essence of the unforeseen, it is the unforeseen itself. You have no idea what the child will grow into, what it will mean for you, and that’s why you have to welcome it. Otherwise you’re only half alive, you’re living like a poor swimmer paddling in the shallows near the shore, while the sea really begins where the water is deep.”

The Farewell Party


There isn’t a person on this planet who is not capable of sending a fellow human being to death without any great pangs of conscience. At least I have never found anyone like that. If humanity ever changes in that regard, it will lose one of its most basic characteristics. Those will no longer be human beings, but creatures of some other type.

The Farewell Party


By turning all of humanity into murderers, your own murders cease to be crimes and become an essential characteristic of the human race!

The Farewell Party


He had finally come around to the position of his more cautious friends. True, the constitution guaranteed freedom of speech; but the law punished any act that could be construed as undermining the state. Who could tell when the state would start screaming that this or that word was undermining it? He decided he’d better put the incriminating papers in a safe place after all.

The Book of Laughter and Forgetting



Tuesday, 8 October 2013

VALUES, VALUE JUDGMENTS AND FACTS — PART 2


Now, what I want is, Facts. Teach these boys and girls nothing but Facts. Facts alone are wanted in life. Plant nothing else, and root out everything else. You can only form the minds of reasoning animals upon Facts: nothing else will ever be of any service to them. This is the principle on which I bring up my own children, and this is the principle on which I bring up these children. Stick to Facts, sir!
Hard Times — Charles Dickens.


THE RIGHT HONOURABLE THE EARL RUSSELL

Sceptical Essays Bertrand Russell
But there is another ingredient, equally essential, but absent in the  Middle Ages, and not common in antiquity—namely, an interest in ‘irreducible  and stubborn facts’ Curiosity about facts is found before the Renaissance in individuals—for example, the Emperor Frederick II and Roger Bacon; but at the Renaissance it suddenly becomes common among intelligent  people. In Montaigne one finds it without the interest in Natural Law; consequently Montaigne was not a man of science. A peculiar blend of general and particular interests is involved in the pursuit of science; the particular is studied in the hope that it may throw light upon the general. In the Middle Ages it was thought that, theoretically, the particular could be reduced from the general principles; in the Renaissance these general principles fell into disrepute and the passion for historical antiquity produced a strong interest in particular occurrences This interest, operating upon minds trained by the Greek, Roman and scholastic traditions, produced at last the mental atmosphere which made Kepler and Galileo possible. But naturally something of this atmosphere surrounds their work and has travelled with it down to their present-day successors. ‘Science has never shaken off its origin in historical revolt of the later Renaissance. It has remained predominantly an anti-rationalistic movement, based upon naïve  faith. What reasoning it has wanted has been borrowed from mathematics, which is a surviving relic of Greek rationalism, following the deductive method. Science repudiates philosophy. In other words, it has never cared to justify its faith or to explain its meaning, and has remained blandly indifferent to its refutation by Hume.’
    Can science survive when we separate it from the superstitions which nourished its infancy? The indifference of science to philosophy has been due, of course, to its amazing success; it has increased the sense of human power, and has therefore been on the whole agreeable, in spite of its occasional conflicts with theological orthodoxy. But in quite recent times science has been driven by its own problems to take an interest in philosophy. This is especially true of the theory of relativity, with its merging of space and time into the single space-time order of events. But it is true also of the theory of quanta, with its apparent need of discontinuous motion. Also, in another sphere, physiology and bio-chemistry are making inroads on psychology which threaten philosophy in a vital spot; Dr Watson's Behaviourism is the spear-head of this attack, which, while it involves the opposite of respect for philosophic tradition, nevertheless necessarily rests upon a new philosophy of its own. For such reasons science and philosophy can no longer preserve an armed neutrality, but  must be either friends or foes. They cannot be friends, they be friends unless science can pass the examination which philosophy must set as to its premisses. If they cannot be friends, they can only destroy each other; it is no longer possible that either alone can remain master of the field.
    Dr Whitehead offers two things, with a view to the philosophical justification of science. On the one hand, he presents certain new concepts, by means of which the physics of relativity and quanta can be built up in a way which is more satisfying intellectually than any that results from piecemeal amendments to the old conception of solid matter. This part of his work, though not yet developed with the fullness that we may hope to see, lies within science as broadly conceived, and is capable of justification by the usual methods which lead us to prefer one theoretical interpretation of a set of facts to another. It is technically difficult, and I shall say no more about it. From our present point of view, the important aspect of Dr Whitehead's work is its more philosophical portion. He not only offers us a better science, but a philosophy which is to make that science rational, in a sense in which traditional science has not been rational since the time of Hume. This philosophy is, in the main, very similar to that of Bergson. The difficulty which I feel here is that, in so far as Dr Whitehead's new concepts can be embodied in formulae which can be submitted to the ordinary scientific or logical tests, they do not seem to involve his philosophy; his philosophy, therefore, must be accepted on its intrinsic merits. We must not accept it merely on the ground that, if true, it justifies science, for the question at issue is whether science can be justified. We must examine directly whether it seems to us to be true in fact; and here we find ourselves beset with all the old perplexities.

Sceptical Essays Bertrand Russell
In spite of the pragmatist's definition of 'truth', however, he has always, in ordinary life, a quite different standard for the less refined questions which arise in practical affairs. A pragmatist on a jury in a murder case will weigh the evidence exactly as any other man will, whereas if he adopted his professed criterion he ought to consider whom among the population it would be most profitable to hang. That man would be, by definition, guilty of the murder, since belief in his guilt would be more useful, and therefore more' true', than belief in the guilt of anyone else. I am afraid such practical pragmatism does sometimes occur; I have heard of 'frame-ups' in America and Russia which answered this description. But in such cases all possible efforts after concealment are made, and if they fail there is a scandal. This effort after concealment shows that even policemen believe in objective truth in the case of a criminal trial. It is this kind of objective truth—a very mundane and pedestrian affair—that is sought in science. It is this kind also that is sought in religion so long as people hope to find it. It is only when people have given up the hope of proving that religion is true in a straightforward sense that they set to work to prove that it is 'true' in some new­fangled sense. It may be laid down broadly that irrationalism, i.e., disbelief in objective fact, arises almost always from the desire to assert something for which there is no evidence, or to deny something for which there is very good evidence. But the belief in objective fact always persists as regards particular practical questions, such as investments or engaging servants. And if fact can be made the test of the truth of our beliefs anywhere, it should be the test everywhere, leading to agnosticism wherever it cannot be applied.
    The above considerations are, of course, very inadequate to their theme. The question of the objectivity of fact has been rendered difficult by the obfuscations of philosophers, with which I have attempted to deal elsewhere in a more thorough­going fashion. For the present I shall assume that there are facts, that some facts can be known, and that in regard to certain others a degree probability can be ascertained in relation to facts which can be known. Our beliefs are, however, often contrary to fact; even when we only hold that something is probable on the evidence, it may be that we ought to hold it to be improbable on the same evidence. The theoretical part of rationality, then, will consist in basing our beliefs as regards matters of fact upon evidence rather than upon wishes, prejudices, or traditions. According to the subject-matter, a rational man will be the same as one who is judicial or one who is scientific.
     There are some who think that psycho-analysis has shown the impossibility of being rational in our beliefs, by pointing out the strange and almost lunatic origin of many people's cherished convictions. I have a very high respect for psycho-analysis, and I believe that it can be enormously useful. But the popular mind has somewhat lost sight of the purpose which has mainly inspired Freud and his followers. Their method is primarily one of therapeutics, a way of curing hysteria and various kinds of insanity. During the war psycho-analysis proved to be far the most potent treatment for war-neuroses.

Sunday, 6 October 2013

THE BURDEN OF PROOF IN SOUTH AFRICAN BAIL LAW

Revised from my Post Graduate Diploma in Law Dissertation, UCT (1998), Supervisor: Prof Dirk Van Zyl Smit (Dean)

[Unless otherwise indicated, all statutory citations relate to the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977]



INTRODUCTION

In respect of more serious offences, the legislature placed the onus in bail proceedings squarely on the arrested (s60(11). On the other hand, the implications of the approach adopted in the case law is that, regarding less serious offences, that one should not have regard to an onus and that the proceedings  are inquisitorial with no onus on either the state or the arrested. In other words, under no circumstances is the onus on the State (whether the offences with which the arrested would be charged relate to either serious or less serious offences). This is ostensibly an anomaly in a Constitutional Democracy sporting a Bill of Rights granting the right to bail. But their again, this right is accorded the arrested only if the interests of justice permit. The catchword is “if”, which implies that the right to be released on bail is contingent upon what the interests of justice might permit. In other words, this is a qualified and not an absolute right to be released.


The Common Law

At Common Law, when an arrested applied for bail, the onus was on them to prove e.g., that: the interests of justice did not require their further detention,  they did not have the propensity to commit crimes, would not abscond, endanger the safety of the public (or any particular person), influence or interfere with witnesses, conceal evidence, obstruct the cause of justice or, etc.

Howard J set out this position in S v Hlongwa 1979 (4) SA 112D in this an oft-quoted passage that has resonated in some of the cases I shall discuss below (e.g., Ellish en Andere vs. Prokureur-Generaal van die Witwatersrandse Afdeling 1994(2) SACR 579 (W) at 590e-f; S v Mbele and Others 1996 (1) SACR 212 (W) at 221b-d).

The accused bears the onus of proving, on a balance of probabilities, that if bail is granted the interests of justice will not be prejudiced by his absconding or tampering with State witnesses.  He will have failed to discharge that onus if, on all the evidence, there is a reasonable possibility that he would tamper with one or more State witnesses if he were released.  The accused's past record, particularly if it includes a conviction for defeating or attempting to defeat the ends of justice by tampering with a State witness, is clearly relevant in this connection and, depending on the circumstances, the court may rely also on the investigating officer's opinion that the accused will interfere with State witnesses, if released on bail, even though his opinion is unsupported by direct evidence. ( Hlongwa at  113h) .

Waddington J in S v Mataboge and Others 1991 (1) SACR 539 (B) reiterated this view:

The onus is upon the applicants for bail to show on a balance of probability that they may safely be released. The applicants are required to show on a balance of probabilities that the interests of justice will not be prejudiced in the sense that it is likely that they  will stand their trial, not tamper with witnesses or otherwise interfere with the investigation of the case against them.  (at 543f)

In Aitken and Another v Attorney-General, Zimbabwe 1992 (2) SACR 296 (ZS) Gubbay J held that “[t]he onus is upon the accused to show on a balance of probabilities why it is in the interests of justice that he should be freed on bail.”  (at 298g). However, the Judge also recognised:

The notion that an accused is presumed innocent until proven guilty is the cornerstone in an application for bail. Consequently, it is the tradition of our courts to lean in favour of and not against the liberty of the subject, and to grant bail where possible (at 298f).


The Transformation

With the enactment of the Interim Constitution, the principles relating to the onus of proof in bail applications that had over the years been taken for granted by our courts, were thrown in disarray. The provision of the Interim Constitution that caused the flurry of judicial decisions was s 25(2)(d).

Every person arrested for the alleged commission of an offence shall, in addition to the rights, which he or she has as a detained person, have the right . . . to be released from detention with or without bail, unless the interests of justice require otherwise.

The right of an arrested person to be released on bail is at present entrenched by section 35(1)(f) of the Republic of South Africa Constitution Act (Act 108 of 1996) (final Constitution). Some decisions discussed in this paper relate to the interpretation of s 25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution and others to s 35(1)(f) of the final Constitution. However, both sections are in essence the same. I shall therefore not embark upon an independent discussion of each section separately. Section 35(1)(f) reads as follows:

Everyone who is arrested for allegedly committing an offence has the right . . . to be released from detention if the interests of justice permit, subject to reasonable conditions)

On 29 April 1994 (a mere two days after the inception of the Interim Constitution), it befell Froneman J to pronounce upon the burden of proof in bail proceedings in the matter of S v Maki (1). 1994(2) SACR 630 (E) at p640c-f. As the background to his judgment preceded the inception of the Interim Constitution, the impact of s25(2)(d) on the burden of proof in bail proceedings could not be considered as such. Despite this, Froneman J concluded that the burden of proof was on the State. The Judge held that the development in our law even in the years preceding our new constitutional dispensation had gravitated towards placing the onus upon the person executing the arrest to prove the lawfulness thereof. Even in the wake of the draconian laws of yore, the then highest court in our country, the Appellate Division, held that the person who effected the arrest, had to prove the lawfulness of thereof. In this regard Froneman J referred to Minister of Law and Order and Others v Hurley and Another 1986 (3) SA 568 (A) at 586j-589i.

The Judge held that the arrested person was not only relieved of having to prove the unlawfulness of his arrest, but that the State had to prove the lawfulness of the detention as well. In this regard the Judge referred to the opinions in Minister van Wet en Orde v Matshoba 1990 (1) SA 280 (A) and During NO v Boesak and Another 1990 (3) SA 661 (A).

The authorities cited by Froneman J related to the rights of persons detained under the Security Legislation of our old oppressive legal order. However, the Judge projected the progressive values expressed in these decisions onto the law relating to the burden of proof in bail proceedings. There could find no valid reason why there should be a difference. After all, the fundamental presumption of innocence extant in our legal system bolsters  this argument. Granted, in bail proceedings regard much be had to considerations of proper administration of justice, i.e., the importance to secure the presence of the accused at the trial and avoiding the obstruction of justice.  These considerations do not necessarily come into play in other forms of depravation of freedom. This means is that in given situations the burden which the State is saddled with could possibly be discharged easier in bail applications as in other matters. In the result, Froneman J concluded that the burden of proof was on the State.


The Revolution

One of the first cases in which it fell squarely to be decided what effect s 25(2)(d) had on the Common law position regarding the onus in bail applications, was Magano and Another v District Magistrate, Johannesburg  and  Others (1)  (1994(2) SACR 304 (W). Van Blerk J held that s25(2)(d) brought about a change in the law, i.e., that the burden was no longer on the arrested, but the Prosecution.

The language of the section does not merely give to an accused person the right to apply for bail, which he has under the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977, but the right 'to be released from detention with or without bail'. That right may only be denied an accused person where 'the interests of justice require otherwise'. The use of the word 'unless' adds weight to the argument that the onus rests upon the  G  State to establish that the interests of justice require the continued detention of an accused. See, for example, R v Liebman 1906 TS 473 at 475; R v Zondagh 1931 AD 8 at 114-15. For these reasons I am of the view that an accused person does not bear the onus to prove that he should be released from detention, but that the State is required to show that he should be refused such bail because the interests of justice require it (at 306f-g).

Stegman J in S v Mbele and Others 1996 (1) SACR 212 (W) looked askance at this approach, labelling it ‘revolutionary’. According to Stegman J the mischief which s 25(2)(d) sought to remedy was to put an end to the powers of the legislature to infringe upon the right of a detained to approach the court for relief. The intention was also to put an end to the power of the legislature or the executive to erode the jurisdiction of the courts to pronounce upon the validity of the detention. What the framers of the interim Constitution never had in mind, was to interfere with the basic principles of the law relating to bail and particularly the incidence of the burden of proof. The Judge held that it was incorrect to interpret the word ‘unless’ in s 25(2)(d) as assigning law-making powers to the judiciary. This, Stegman J held, was what Van Blerk J did in Magano. The Judge proceeded to criticise this approach as follows:
This was, if I may be permitted a respectful comment, a revolutionary step in the law relating to bail. By assuming law-making powers, a member of the judiciary reversed the incidence of the well-established onus of persuading a court in a bail application. In my respectful view there was no sufficient reason to believe that the intention of the framers of the interim Constitution was to revolutionise the settled law relating to bail in that way, or to invest the judiciary  B  with such law-making powers. On the contrary, it is clear to me that the interim Constitution is based upon the doctrine of the separation of the powers of Legislature, Executive and Judiciary; that, leaving aside the special position of the Constitutional Court, the judiciary has not been invested with legislative powers; and  C  that, by means of s 25(2)(d), the framers of the Constitution wished to protect and entrench the rights of all persons under the ordinary and settled law relating to bail by precluding the Legislature or the Executive from preventing anyone from enjoying the benefit of those rights (save for such legislative adjustments as  D  would not conflict with the Constitution). That could only be achieved by ensuring that the power to decide on bail always remains within the exclusive jurisdiction of judicial officers. That is so obvious that it hardly needs to be spelt out (at 234i-235d).


The Counter-Revolution

During 24 and 27 April 1994 (the run-up the first democratic general election) a group of right wing extremists unleashed a spate of bomb explosions in the then Transvaal. Many people died, many more were seriously injured, and damage to the tune of R75 000 000-00 was caused. Upon their arrest, the accused applied for bail in the Regional Court and their application was heard between 15 and 20 May 1994 by Regional Magistrate C J van Heerden. If by their deeds the accused had intended to cause a revolution, they had failed. But what they could not have foreseen when they had hatched their vicious plots, were that their court battles to be released on bail would unleash a battle of another kind, i.e., the debate as to whether or not the concept of  ‘onus’ had the right of existence in our law relating to bail. This was the backdrop to two significant judgments delivered by the Witwatersrand Local Division: Prokureur-Generaal van die Witwatersrandse Afdeling v Van Heerden en Andere  (1994(2) SACR 467 (W)) and Ellish en Andere v Prokureur-Generaal van die Witwatersrandse Afdeling   (1994(2) SACR 579 (W)).

But the first volleys in support of the approach adopted in the Van Heerden and Ellish-cases, had already been fired prior to these judgments in the works of at least two influential writers: Hiemstra, Suid-Afrikaanse Strafproses (5th ed. by J Kriegler),1994, Butterworths)and M. G. Cowling (Law Reform: Bail and the search for a new theoretical approach (some comments and suggestions on the Law Commission's working paper). The views of  these authors questioning the justification for having a niche in our law relating to bail for a concept such as a burden of proof, were favourably rererred to in the Van Heerden and Ellish decisions. The procedure is essentially inquisitorial in character, the presiding judicial officer (who cannot just sit back and receive whatever evidence the parties wished or were able to tender) to direct the proceedings and to ensure that sufficient information is placed before the court so that a proper decision can be reached. At times corroborating evidence on, e.g., an accused's personal background or previous convictions might have to actively seek. This inquisitorial-type procedure renders the question of onus irrelevant although in more general terms the State has to produce valid reasons why release should be denied. If, at the end of the weighing-up and balancing process such reasons are found not to exist, the accused is entitled to be released. (For Hiemstra, see the Van Heerden-case at 479g,, as well as Ellish-case at 585 e-f); for Cowling, see the Ellish-case at 585a-d).

Eloff J in Van Heerden held that the reason why regard should not be had to the concept of onus is that bail proceedings were not criminal but judicial proceedings. The question of onus is important in criminal proceedings against an accused. It not at all has a comparable role in an investigation into the advisability to release an arrested person (at 479e).

It was held, however, that the duty to initiate proceedings rested on the prosecution. The reason was that if the State wished to oppose bail, it is only logical and fair that the prosecutor should motivate and substantiate its reasons for its opposition by initiating the proceedings. If the State presented evidence that was of such a nature that an explanation on the part of the accused were required, the accused could then adduce evidence in response to that of by the State. If the accused failed to adduce evidence in rebuttal, the court could draw a negative inference. Viewed thus, Eloff J held, there existed a burden of rebuttal, the nature of which had to be shaped by practical and equitable considerations. (Van Heerden-case (supra) at 480d-e).

Then the Attorney-General of the Witwatersrand Provincial Division, having succeeded in his appeal to have the judgment of Regional Magistrate Van Heerden overturned in the Van Heerden-case, came up against an appeal brought by the accused. The Full Bench in the Ellish-case (supra) dismissed the appeal. In the majority judgment Schalkwyk J (Mynardt J concurring), held that bail proceedings were sui generis in nature, e.g., evidence could be presented on an informal basis, it could be presented by means of  hearsay or documentary evidence and an accused could motivate his application by means of affidavit.

The  test applied to each an every bail application was, however, aimed at probable future conduct of the detained person i.e., whether he would stand his trial, whether there is a likelihood that he would interfere with State witnesses or obstruct the course of justice, whether their is a likelihood that he would commit offences while awaiting trial, etc. The court held that in the past, as well as at present, no bail application could be held without giving due consideration to one or more of these factors. It was the duty of the presiding officer, the issue of onus notwithstanding, to ensure that justice prevailed. The presiding officer had to satisfy him or herself that the right of the arrested to be released should be weighed up against the interests that the community to protection. This, Van Schalkwyk J held, could not be achieved when a presiding officer was a mere onlooker F (at 585f- 586b).

Like Eloff J in Van Heerden, Van Schalkwyk held that it was incumbent upon the state to initiate the proceedings. If there were an equilibrium between the interests of the accused on the one hand and the interests of justice on the other, then the accused would be entitled to be released. This right, Van Schalkwyk J held, emanated from the provisions of s 25(2)(d), and was not the result of the application of an onus.  (at 591f-g

In a minority judgment, Southwood J agreed that the appeal should be dismissed, but disagreed with the majority of the court that s 25(2)(d) did not create an onus that the state had to discharge.  Having adopted the approach that the accused had a right to be released on bail in terms of s 25(2)(d) (unless it is proved that the interests of justice required otherwise), Southwood J proceeded as follows:

It cannot be expected of the arrested person who has a right to be released from detention with or without bail to prove that his release is not contrary to the interests of justice or that the interests of justice do not require his release. This must be shown by the person who, or authority which seeks his continued detention in the face of such right. This is the only reasonable construction which can be placed on the  wording of the subsection itself.  (at 595i-j).

Southwood J agreed with the view of the majority of the court that it is incumbent upon the prosecution to initiate proceedings. However, the Judge was of the opinion that once the State is called upon to lead evidence first, it has a crucial impact on the whole question as to whether or not s 25(2)(d) created an onus:

I agree that if at the end of the enquiry the scales are evenly balanced then the person arrested is entitled to be released with or without bail and that the State must lead evidence first in bail proceedings and this is based on the proper construction to be placed on the subsection. However, this construction is crucial to the issue which had to be decided, i.e. whether or not the subsection creates an onus or not. (my emphasis).  (at 596c-d).

Southwood J held that in a bail application, the question as to whether or not a person is entitled to be released is of vital interest both to the arrested as well as the State and both parties were entitled to lead evidence. The fact that bail proceedings were sui generis and inquisitorial in nature did not affect the fact that the presiding officer may, on the evidence presented, find that the further detention of the accused would be in the interests of justice. To make use of an onus to resolve this issue would be both practical and juridically sound (see 596d-e).

Southwood J furthermore held that the use of an onus would not change the nature of the bail proceedings. Historically, the courts accepted that the onus was on the arrested and this did not have any effect on the inquisitorial nature of those proceedings. With the Interim Constitution in force, there was no justification to believe that the court will now cease to play the role it played prior of the implementation of the Constitution merely if the onus were shifted to the State. The court only had to continue the active role it had played over the years prior to the Constitution:

 G As long as the court bears in mind that it is not required to simply play a passive role, the use of an onus will not result in any  I  injustice. In any event even on the approach of Van Schalkwyk J injustices may arise if the court simply plays a passive role in bail proceedings. I fully agree with Van Schalkwyk J that a court hearing an application for the release of a detained person must always bear in mind that its task is to ensure that justice is done  (at  596h-i).

Leveson J in the Mbele-case criticised the judgment of Van Schalkwyk in Ellish for concluding that bail proceedings were inquisitorial in nature. According to Leveson J there were no juridical foundation for his conclusion. The Judge held that, ‘[n]o power was given in the Constitution Act to the judicial officer to act as inquisitor and as far as my researches have taken me, nowhere at the time of the Ellish judgment, or since, has it anywhere been laid down that the proceedings are inquisitorial’ (at 217b).

In dealing with the practical implications of abolition of the onus in bail applications, Leveson J drew attention to the resemblance opposed bail proceedings have to actual trials. While the Judge conceded that a court is called upon to give judgment on ‘the probable future conduct of the detained person’  (Worded as follows by Van Schalkwyk J in the Ellish-case (supra) at 585f: ‘die waarskynlike toekomstige optrede van die aangehoudene., he was not convinced that the task of the presiding officer is more onerous than that performed in any other trial. Even the minority judgment of Southwood J came in for criticism for concluding that s 25(2)(d) had shifted the onus on to the State.

There are averments to be proved or disproved, as the  E  case may be, and when there is doubt there is no reason why the matter should not be resolved by resorting to the expedient of onus. It is true also that the court is required to form an opinion as to a man's future conduct. In this connection there is no reason to expect a judicial officer to be more skilled in clairvoyance than any other person. But even with future prospects the court must attempt to judge them in  F  relation to present facts. There has to be determination of an issue as in any other trial. I am not persuaded that the factors considered by the learned Judge in the Ellish case carry any weight, first, because there is nothing in s 25(2)(d) which invites their application, and second, because there was no reason to overthrow  at least 60 years of decisions in which it had been held that the onus lay on the  G  accused. The correctness of the view of the majority of the Court is thus open to doubt. For the record it should be added that in the minority judgment of Southwood J it was said that the onus lay on the State. With that view I obviously disagree (at 217d-g).

The judgments of Leveson J and Stegman J in S v Mbele were all embracing and relatively lengthy. It dealt with the common law, it dealt with, and criticised, the ‘revolutionary step’ taken by Van Blerk AJ in S v Mgano, and then proceeded to criticise both the majority and minority judgments in Ellish. Although Ellish was a full bench decision to which Stegman J conceded, ‘I respectfully acknowledge this Court to be bound’  (at 237a), both Judges were nevertheless highly critical of, and rejected the conclusions reached in Ellish.

I have already mentioned the criticism by Stegman J of the Magano-case and the label given to it i.e., ‘revolutionary’  (supra). This is how Stegman J referred to the judgment of the full bench in Ellish:

However,  the revolutionary step taken in Magano's case resulted  E  in what I would respectfully characterise as a counter-revolutionary step taken in Prokureur-generaal van die Witwatersrandse Plaaslike Afdeling v Van Heerden en Andere 1994 (2) SACR 469 (W), and by the majority of a Full Court in Ellish en Andere v Prokureur-generaal, WPA 1994 (2) SACR 579 (W). (at 236d-e).

In Mbele, the  Magano-case was adjudged ‘revolutionary’ by Stegman J for the following reasons: the law prior to the Interim Constitution was to the effect that an arrested person in a bail application had the onus to persuade the court that it would be in the interests of justice to release him; this, it was held in the Magano-case, to be in conflict with s 25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution. The onus rested on the State. Then Ellish-case, in turn, was pronounced ‘counter-revolutionary’ for holding that ‘a bail application is to be conducted without either the applicant or the respondent having any burden to persuade the court about how the interests of justice will best be served.‘  (at p236g).

Under the law as stated before  27 April 1994, replete with the wisdom of two or three generations of Judges, an applicant for his release with or without bail pending his trial would fail unless he succeeded in persuading a court that the interests of justice which favoured the protection of his liberty outweighed the interests of justice which would be put at risk by his release (at 236i-j).

With the pronouncement of the Ellish-decision, ‘that accumulated wisdom has ceased to reflect the law’ at least according to Stegman J (at p237a).. The Judge gave the following scenario of the practical implications if no onus were applied, and where the presiding officer took full charge of the proceedings:

The applicant is no longer required to persuade the court to release him. Neither is the Attorney General or his representative, as the respondent,  B  required to persuade the court not to release him. It is all left to the magistrate or Judge who is to decide the issue. He must take the initiative and conduct an inquisitorial proceeding. If the first stages  of his inquiry reveal a more or less equal balance between those interests of justice which favour the release of the applicant with or without bail, and those interests of justice which do not,  C  the inquisitor is presumably required to keep on digging until his enquiries satisfy him one way or the other. As the present case has shown, the effective discharge of the role of inquisitor or  D  investigator is going to make it difficult in many cases to preserve a judicial impartiality, or even the appearance of it (at 237a-d).



Legislating and the Burden of Proof

In 1995 legislation was introduced (s 60(11) to make it more difficult for those  charged with serious offences to be granted bail―if at all. Subsequently the Legislature again amendment the Criminal Procedure Act  (the Criminal Procedure Second Amendment Act 85 of 1997) with a view to tightening up our bail law even further. What the legislation in effect did, was to place the onus on the arrested to satisfy the court that the interests of justice did not require their further detention. This amendment came into operation as from 1 August 1998. Some all the authorities cited in this paper revolve around the interpretation of the original s 60(11). However, the amended s 60(11) does not impact upon the incidence of the burden of proof. Only the manner in which the burden should be discharged is being affected i.e., the arrested person must discharge the onus by adducing evidence. Therefore, where the old s 60(11) is referred to in passages from decisions quoted below, the interpretation given to the old measure should, with the necessary changes in mind, be projected upon the new one.

Section 60(11) as amended by  Act 85 of 1997 now reads as follows:

Notwithstanding any provision of this Act, where an accused is charged with an offence referred to-
(a)  in Schedule 6, the court shall order that the accused be detained in custody until he or she is dealt with in accordance with the law, unless the accused, having been given a reasonable opportunity to do so, adduces evidence which satisfies the court that exceptional circumstances exist which in the interests of justice permit his or her release;
(b) in Schedule 5, but not in Schedule 6, the court shall order that the accused be detained in custody until he or she is dealt with in accordance with the law, unless the accused, having been given a reasonable opportunity to do so, adduces evidence which satisfies the court that the interests of justice permit his or her release.

When the effect of s60(11) on the incidence of proof in bail proceedings fell to be decided by our courts, Mbele  once again featured prominently. In fact, the effect of s60(11) on the incidence of proof in bail proceedings was the ratio decidendi of Mbele. It was only in the course of interpreting this subsection that the Judges saw it fit to comment on the full bench decision of Ellish to which they conceded they were bound anyway. As we have seen, Leveson J and Stegman J (even without the assistance of this recent legislative directive) were adamant that s25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution had not effected a shift of the burden of proof from the State to the accused. Given this legislative support, therefore, the Judges had no difficulty to conclude that the new legislation squarely put the onus on the arrested person.

Thus spoke Leveson J:

There is perhaps a tendency to avoid the use of the expression 'burden of proof'  I  because a bail application is not a criminal proceeding and because the court is not required to weigh proved facts but to speculate on future conduct on the basis of information laid before it. But it is clear from the cases cited in the judgment of Van Schalkwyk J in the Ellish case and the cases cited herein that 'onus' is a well-known concept in bail proceedings. I do not think there is any purpose in being coy about the use of the word or that courts should shrink from using it simply because of the nature of the proceeding. If a statute casts upon a party the duty of satisfying the court on a particular point then whatever language is used he has an onus. And, for the purpose of a bail application, the accused has the onus of   J
establishing that the granting of bail is in the interests of justice and for that limited purpose the word must have the meaning given in Pillay v Krishna and Another 1946 AD 946 at 952, aptly quoted in the minority judgment of Southwood J in the Ellish case.

In my opinion the current legislation squarely places the question of onus where it  B  has always belonged - on the accused - . . .  (at 220i-221b).

The incidence of proof, having been assigned thus, Stegman J held that, as far as the facts of the case were concerned, it had been impermissible for the magistrate to act inquisitorially.  The magistrate, having applied the principles laid down in the Ellish-case, had misdirected himself in doing this, because Ellish had been decided before s60(11) was enacted. The Ellish-case only applied to that category of cases that did not fall within the ambit of the offences with which s60(11) was concerned.  Stegman J said the following:

8.   In the present matter the appellants were charged with offences referred to in the new Schedule 5 of Act 51 of 1977. The magistrate held the consequence to be that the new
9.   s 60(11) imposed on them the onus of satisfying him that the interests of justice did not require their detention in custody. In adopting this approach the magistrate was undoubtedly correct.  I
    
9.  Relying on Ellish's case the magistrate acted inquisitorially or investigatively, and in so doing he descended for a period into the arena of conflict between the appellants and the State.
In my judgment this was an error. Ellish's case was decided before the new s 60(11) placed an  onus upon a bail applicant who falls within its provisions. Ellish's case continues to govern bail applications that are not regulated by s 60(11). But where s 60(11) is applicable, the applicant for bail undoubtedly has an onus to discharge; there is no room for the application of the decision in Ellish's case; and there is accordingly no warrant for any inquisitorial or investigative action on the part of the judicial officer hearing the application (at 237i-238a).
It is now generally accepted by our Courts that s 60(11) places the burden of proof on the arrested to satisfy the court that the interests of justice do not require their further detention.  (Compare: S v Vermaas 1996 (1) SACR 528 (T) per van Dijkhorst J at p528h; S v Shezi 1996 (1) SACR 715 (T)  per Els J at p718a).


The Standard of Proof

The fact that the s 60(11) placed the onus on the arrested, did not mean that this burden is now more onerous than it had been before s 60(11) came into operation. The arrested only has to prove that the interests of justice did not require their further detention. Traverso J in S v Stanfield   1997 (1) SACR 221 (C) (at 226g-h) held that a test higher than this would render the onus almost impossible for the person to discharge and therefore justiciable on constitutional grounds.

If the standard of proof to be applied is the same as it had been prior to the enactment of s 60(11), then the views expressed in the judgments mentioned above should apply. This standard is ‘proof on a balance of probabilities’, not ‘proof beyond reasonable doubt’. See, for example, the judgment of   Howard J in S v Hlongwa (supra) which is to the effect that ‘[t]he accused bears the onus of proving, on a balance of probabilities, that if bail is granted the interests of justice will not be prejudiced by his absconding or tampering with State witnesses.’  See also the passage by Waddington J in S v Mataboge and Other (supra)  thatThe onus is upon the applicants for bail to show on a balance of probability that they may safely be released.”



The Constitutionality of Section 60(11)

The judgments in Mbele once again feature prominently during the debate on the constitutionality of s 60(1). As I have already pointed out, Stegman J adopted the approach that s 25(2)(d) had nothing whatsoever to do with the incidence of any risk of persuasion. The mischief that the framers of the Constitution had intended to address, was the removal from our legal system of the draconian legislation which provided for the detention of persons by the Executive with impunity, whilst placing prohibitions the arrested person to approach a court of law to apply for his release.
Thus spoke Stegman J:
What emerges from this discussion is the important point that s 25(2)(d) of the interim Constitution does not deal with the  E  question of onus in a bail application at all. There is therefore no question of any such conflict between s 25(2)(d) of the interim Constitution and the new s 60(11) of Act 51 of 1977 as Mr. Stander postulated in his argument. This would remain the  F  position even if Ellish's case were one day to be reconsidered. On any basis, s 25(2)(d) of the interim Constitution does not deal with the question of onus at all, expressly or by implication.
On the other hand, the new s 60(11) plainly and unambiguously places an onus upon certain accused persons to satisfy a court  G  that those interests of justice which favour their release pending a trial, outweigh the interests of justice which are adverse to their release (at 237d-i).

In Mbele Leveson J also held that s 60(11) did not infringe upon the principles embedded in s 25(2)(d). The judge expressed the view that s 25(2)(d) merely essentially recited the right of the individual to his freedom; there were no prescription for any procedural provisions for the determination of that right. The subsection  did prohibit the introduction of legislation placing the burden on either the State or the arrested. Being neutral in character, this subsection neither empowered nor prohibited (at 218b). Leveson J was. however, alive to the scope and breath of the constitutional debate unfolding around him.

It is abundantly clear that the section contains a direction that, pending the outcome of the proceedings and order that might follow, the accused is to be detained in custody.  However he is given the right to satisfy the court that the interests of justice do not require his detention.  Clearly that implies that he must initiate the application and be given a hearing although there is a provision that in a case where the accused is not represented the magistrate may invite him to apply for bail.  On the face of it a direction that the accused be detained in custody appears to be in conflict with s 25(2)(d) which prescribes that a detained person is to be released with or without bail.  But I think it more proper to read the whole section as being adjectival, i.e. as simply requiring that in order to be released from detention the accused must satisfy the court that it is in the interests of justice that this be done. (my emphasis)  (at p218h-219a per Leveson J)

The judgment of Leveson J  (at  218h-219a) in Mbele did not appeal to Edeling J in Prokureur-Generaal, Vrystaat v Ramokhosi  1997 (1) SACR 127 (0) (at 152g) either. Edeling J pointed out that Leveson J conceded  (at 218j of  Mbele) that s 60(11) of the Criminal Procedure Act was on the face of it in conflict with s 25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution. Edeling J, however, criticised Leveson J for brushing this conflict off “as simply requiring that in order to be released from detention the accused must satisfy the court that it is in the interests of justice that this be done”. C
Edeling J was of the opinion that s 60(11) is in direct conflict with both s 60(1)(a) as well as s 25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution and that the issue had best be pronounced upon by the Constitutional Court. The Judge acknowledged that he could not pronounce upon the constitutionality of s 60(11). He was, therefore bound to work on the assumption that s 60(11) placed the burden of proof upon the arrested (at 153c-g).

In S v Shezi 1996 (1) SACR 715 (T) Els J was also of the opinion that s 60(11) was not in conflict with s 25(2)(d). The reason advanced was that s 60(11) was enacted in order to make it more difficult for certain people who are under arrest and who are charged with having committed certain serious offences, more difficult to get bail (at 717e).



SUMMARY

The debate on the burden proof in bail proceedings, is confusing. Van Blerk AJ in Magano, was of opinion that s 25(2)(d) of the Interim Constitution reversed the burden of proof i.e., the State is required to show that an arrested should be refused such bail because the interests of justice required this. Eloff J in Van Heerden held that one cannot refer to a concept of ‘onus’. The reason is that neither the State nor the arrested had the onus to prove that the interests of justice required further detention or release (as the case may be). The proceedings were inquisitorial.

The burden to initiate the proceedings, however, rested on the State. On appeal both Van Schalkwyk J and Mynhardt J in Ellish upheld the decision of Eloff J in Van Heerden. In the minority judgment Southwood J disagreed with the finding of the majority that the onus should be dispensed with; the Judge held that the onus rested on the State. He did, however, endorse the view of the majority that the proceedings were inquisitorial.

Both Judges in Mbele, disagreed with each and every opinion outlined above. It was held that Magano was incorrectly decided, because s 25(2)(d) did not shift the onus to the State. The criticisms levelled at both Van Heerden and Ellish were that historically there had not been justification for such an approach: bail proceedings were inquisitorial and it is furthermore not necessary have regard to a burden of proof.  Although obiter, the judgment in the Mbele has highlighted the strands of opinion that constitute the slippery nature of the burden of proof in bail applications. The legislation that was introduced added another strand, complicating the debate even further. Initially there had been uncertainty as to the constitutionality of s 60(11). In Mbele and Shezi it was held that s 60(11) was not in conflict with s25(2)(d) of the Interim. Edeling J in Ramokhosi (an orbiter opinion) was of the opinion that s 60(11) was in conflict with the Constitution and justiciable on that ground.

Where an arrested is charged with an offence not listed in either Schedules 5 or 6 and in respect of which the ‘reverse onus’ provision of s 60(11) therefore does not apply, there is no onus either on the state the arrested, because the proceedings would be inquisitorial. Under these circumstances, the law as laid down in Ellish is applicable—it was a full bench Decision and thus far the most authoritative constituted court to have considered the issue. There is, In other words, no burden of proof; although the prosecution has to initiate proceedings. The proceedings are inquisitorial and the presiding officer plays an active role throughout. At the end the court will merely weigh up the quality of the evidence adduced—mindful of course that there is no onus and neither party receives the benefit in the event of doubt.

Where an arrested is charged with a serious offence listed in Schedules 5 or 6, the ‘reverse onus’ provision of s 60(11) applies, i.e., they must prove that their further detention would not be in the interests of justice by adducing evidence that (exceptional circumstances existed which in) the interests of justice permit their release.”   In respect of schedule 5 offences, only the requirement outside the brackets applies; with regard to schedule 6 offences, the bracketed text also forms part of the test.


CONCLUSION: A FootNote’s  Worth

The Constitutional Court in S v Dlamini; S v Dladla and Others; S v Joubert; S v Schietekat 1999 (2) SACR 51 (CC) all but settled the onus debate as regards s60(11), upholding its constitutionality. But in all fairness to Kriegler J, let me hasten to add that the Constitutional Court Judge actually gave a wide berth to the term “onus” as such, euphemistically stating that there is “a burden cast upon an applicant for bail”. [par 45 note 74―quoted more fully below]. Be this as it may, let me first deal with Kriegler’s J’s endorsement of the constitutionality of s60 (11) through the following excerpts:


[78]      . . . It was not suggested that the imposition of an onus on an applicant for bail is in itself constitutionally objectionable, nor could such a submission have been sustained.  This Court has in the past unhesitatingly struck down provisions that created a reverse  onus carrying the risk of conviction despite the existence of a reasonable doubt; but what we have here is not a reverse onus of that kind.  Here there is no risk of a wrong conviction, the objection that lies at the root of the unacceptability of reverse onuses.  All that the subsection does in this regard, is to place on an accused, in whose knowledge the relevant factors lie, an onus to establish them in a special kind of interlocutory proceeding not geared to arriving at factual conclusions but designed to make informed prognoses.

[79]      . . . Section 60(11)(a) therefore does not create an onus where nothing of the kind existed before.  It describes how it is to be discharged, and adds to its weight.  As in the case of reliance on any other right in the Bill of Rights, if accused persons wish to rely on the provisions of s 35(1)(f), they must bring themselves within its ambit.  The words “interests of justice permit” form part of the definition of this right; they delineate its ambit.  The court must be satisfied that “the interests of justice permit” the release from detention.  Where all the relevant facts are common cause, the matter is decided by the presiding judicial officer exercising a value judgment according to all the relevant criteria on the basis of these facts in the manner described in this judgment.  If facts indispensable for establishing that the interests of justice permit the arrestee’s release are not established, the arrestee is not entitled to the remedy under the subsection.

On the other hand, perhaps because the question of onus (or “burden cast upon an applicant for bail” for that matter) with regard to offences not governed by s60(11) had not been up for consideration as such, Kriegler J (à la Pontius Pilate) all but washed his hands off this particular aspect―relegating it to a mere footnote.

I avoid using the word “onus” in order not to get involved in the debate (see eg Ellish en Andere v Prokureur-Generaal, Witwatersrandse Plaaslike Afdeleing 1994 (4) SA 835 (W); 1994 (2) SACR 579 (W); S v Vermaas 1996 (1) SACR 528 (T); S v Tshabalala 1998 (2) SACR 259 (C); S v Mbele and Another 1996 (1) SACR 212 (W); S v Shezi 1996 (1) SACR 715 (T)) mentioned at 246A-B of the judgment in Schietekat.  For the present it is unnecessary to resolve the question whether there is an onus in bail proceedings and, if so, its incidence.  The current cases are governed by sub-s (11), where there is undoubtedly a burden cast upon an applicant for bail. [par 45 footnote 74]

So let me conclude that the law on the discussion at hand is that there is “a burden cast upon an applicant for bail” in respect of Schedule 5 and 6 offences. However, as for offences not governed by s60(11) the full bench opinion as laid down in Ellish prevails, i.e., there is not an onus on either the prosecution or the arrested and the proceedings are inquisitorial.